Some Non-Scientific
Observations on the Importance of Darwin
Ian Johnston
Liberal Studies Department
Malaspina-University College, Nanaimo, BC
[now Vancouver Island University]
[The following is the text of a lecture given,
in part, to a group of senior Biology students at Malaspina
University-College, Nanaimo, on October 1, 1998. The text was very slightly
revised in October 2000. This document is in the public domain, released October
1998]
For comments or questions, please
contact Ian Johnston.
A. Introduction
Good afternoon. You will have to forgive me if I look a little
nervous. However, it is not everyday that I venture
into a hotbed of revolutionary radicals bent on overthrowing all traditional
forms of order, young followers of the most disturbing intellectual upheaval
that our culture has ever gone through, spirits dedicated to a cause that has
produced a belief system that has undercut all forms of stability, order, and
customary belief. You do look friendly enough, but I must warn you that I’m on
my guard. My study of the subject you have committed your professional selves
to has taught me to be very careful of biologists,
even when they bear gifts.
Today, I would like to explain to you why I have such apprehension,
why, that is, biology has proven to be such a revolutionary activity, why I
can, with good justification make the claim that no single event in the history
of our culture has had such a devastating effect on our political,
intellectual, religious, and moral life as has the
development of the modern understanding of the world given to us by biologists.
I suspect that some of you may at this stage find those claims
somewhat exaggerated. They are not, and I hope to persuade you that I am right
in characterizing biology in this way. In order to do that I am going to have
to discuss a number of aspects of the history of your discipline, that is, to
acquaint you with some of the features which make modern biology something
which has shaken everything that went before to the foundations.
In order to do that I am going to have to talk about Charles
Darwin, and if you know no history of your subject, you should at least carve
onto the front of your notebook the figure 1859, the year Darwin published Origin
of Species, the year he dropped the bombshell which we are still trying to
deal with.
My concern here is not going to be scientific, although I shall
have to discuss scientific ideas and achievement from time to time. My main
concern here is to explore the wider consequences of Darwin’s ideas, as these
manifest themselves in philosophy, religion, politics, morality, and in
knowledge generally. In doing this, I am not simply seeking to provide you a
lot of background information or pleasant details which will supplement your
scientific studies; I am trying to do something much more than that: to
acquaint you with a problem you are going to have to deal with as professional
biologists.
To make this last point clear, let me put on the table some
curious facts of the modern world. You may be familiar with them, but if you
are not, then you are soon going to be.
1.
First, Darwin’s general theory has become, in association with the
development of genetic theories, the orthodoxy in biology. Of course there are many
vigorous disputes about the details (e.g., the arguments between, say, Dawkins
and Gould, the debates about the sociobiology of Wilson and others) and there
are many issues still to be ironed out. Still, it is virtually impossible to be
a practicing biologists anywhere in the world without
subscribing to Darwin’s theory of natural selection.
2.
Secondly, Darwin’s theory is, of all the great scientific
theories, the easiest for anyone to understand. Any lay person who can read has
immediate access to what Darwin is saying, in a manner that is simply not
possible with the theories of, say, Newton or Einstein or Bohr.
3.
Finally, in spite of this total dominance of the scientific
community and its ready accessibility, Darwin’s theory is totally rejected by
approximately half of the population in North America, one of the best educated
and most scientifically sophisticated societies the world has ever seen. People
have no trouble accepting Newton or Einstein; there is, by contrast, enormous
hostility to Darwin.
It might interest you to know that Darwin himself seems to have
had profound unconscious worries about the consequences of his own theory. He
suffered, as you may know, for most of his life from a mysterious and very
debilitating condition which made his work difficult to carry out. No one has
successfully defined what disease afflicted him, but a number of biographers
have come to the conclusion that it was probably psychosomatic, a deep
psychological distress at the recognition of what the full implications of his
theory might mean. In fact, this worry was clearly an important factor in his
decision to delay publishing his theory for almost fifteen years; he finally
was forced to go public when another natural scientist, Wallace, came up with
the same idea.
This problem of the prejudice against a central tenet of
biological theory should concern you as would-be professional biologists, and
it is far too simple to write that rejection of Darwin off as the result of
ignorance or simple religious prejudice (although that may well be the case
with many people). The fact is that what Darwin did in 1859 was the most
revolutionary act in our intellectual history, and millions of people still
find the consequences unsettling and unacceptable. I am going to attempt to
tell you why.
I welcome the chance to do that because I would like you all to
understand that Darwin’s theory is intellectual dynamite. You are, I assume,
familiar enough with the theory as an organizing principle in modern science.
But if that’s all you understand about Darwin, then
you will be very ill equipped to understand the full implications of his
achievement and, beyond that, the widespread distrust and active hostility
which his theory still encounters and will continue to encounter. As I have
mentioned before, no idea in the history of our culture has such revolutionary
implications. It is no accident that Karl Marx wanted to dedicate his
masterpiece to Darwin or that the destroyer of all philosophical systems,
Friedrich Nietzsche, owed such an enormous debt to the work of this quiet,
middle-class, mildly liberal English naturalist.
To substantiate these claims, I’m going to tell you a story, one
you are probably not all that familiar with. In Liberal Studies a colleague of
mine (who is a scientist) likes to say that for modern scientists the story of
biology begins with Darwin but that the truth is that with Darwin the story
ends. By that he obviously does not mean that there have been no exciting or
important advances in biology since Darwin; he does mean that all of those are
essentially developments of or refinements to what Darwin achieved. The really
exciting period, the truly dramatic and revolutionary story, is the period up
to Darwin. He is the fifth act of the drama, as I hope to demonstrate to you.
B. Some Terminology: Biologists and Darwin
However, before we begin that story, I’d like to clarify a couple
of terms. I began by making all sorts of allegations about biologists. But the
story I am going to tell was conducted largely by people who did not call
themselves that. The terms biology and biologist (which were
coined by an unjustly maligned scientist of major importance, Jean-Baptiste Lamarck), after all, are not yet two hundred years
old. The people I am going to be talking about thought of themselves, for the
most part, as natural scientists, as philosophers with an interest in the
natural world, as people of God looking for evidence of His work in the natural
world. They did not live in a world where knowledge about the world was so
neatly divided into disciplinary components and they moved easily between
religion, philosophy, politics, and natural science because they saw these as
all inextricably interconnected. Many of them, in fact, took up natural science
or encouraged it in order to further their religious or political beliefs. So I
will be using the word natural scientist rather than biologist--not as any
insult to people here present, but simply to remind us all that the stern and
strictly organized discipline suggested by that word biology did not exist in
the period I shall be talking about.
Secondly, I want to clarify what I mean by Darwin. Of course, I
refer the man Charles Darwin, but I also mean all the things that made his work
possible. One of the great problems with a major scientific theory, like Darwin’s
or Newton’s, is that it tends to get all the credit. It throws into an eternal
obscurity the vital work that other natural scientists carried out which made
the great achievement possible. I think it’s probably fair to say that hardly
any major scientific discoveries or theories are carried out in isolation by a
single imagination. They are the result of a wonderfully synthetic imagination
which gathers together into a coherent form the work of a many predecessors and
contemporaries. That is certainly the case with the two most impressive
theories of the modern age, those of Newton and Darwin. And the power and
influence of these theories have encouraged us to forget (or at least to fail
to remember) the many great natural scientists without whose work the theories
would never have appeared. It may be worth remembering that when Darwin
published his theory, Thomas Huxley was staggered at the simplicity and
obviousness of what Darwin was proposing; the intellectual climate, which
others had prepared, had made, in his view, Darwin’s theory inevitable.
However, in celebrating the greatness of Darwin, we often lose sight of those
others.
Anyway, when I use the term Darwin and Darwinism, I would like to
include in that a sense of all those others who contributed (sometimes by their
opposition) to furthering the intellectual movement which made Darwin’s theory
possible.
C. The Revolutionary Basis for Biology: Classification
In order to grasp why Darwin’s theory was so fundamentally
revolutionary, you must understand one intellectual concept: the power and
importance of classification systems. As students of biology you are thoroughly
familiar with the need for classification, at least within your discipline. But
I want you to step back from the discipline for a moment to understand the
importance of classification in general.
It will be obvious enough to you, as biologists,
that you cannot function in this discipline without a comprehensive
system of classification. This is especially the case with biology, and has
always been a central issue in this part of natural science, simply because in
biology, more than in any other science, there is a huge
variety of natural phenomena to deal with. But I would argue that
systems of classification are essential for all human thought and for the same
reasons. Without a classification system of some kind, something which enables
us to compartmentalize similar things and to make distinctions between other
things, we simply cannot function. Providing us a classification system is the
primary function of our education: we learn to classify things in order to make
moral distinctions, to establish the hierarchy of goods and goals for our
lives, to understand the natural world around us, and in order to function as
social beings. How we think is largely determined by how we classify things.
The great systems of belief in religion or philosophy or politics
are classification systems. Christian belief, for example, encourages me to
distinguish between Christians and pagans, between sinners, good people, and
saints; a political classification system tells me whom I must or should obey,
whom I am responsible for, who owes me allegiance, and who I can ignore. And so
on. When I am faced with a problem, I simply cannot begin to analyze it,
understand it, and resolve it unless I first have a classification system
available for understanding it.
The greatest thinkers are not those who come with new answers for
old problems. They are the ones who redefine the problem by putting a new
classification system on the table. Plato did not solve the problem of how to
make people good; but after Plato it was impossible to talk intelligently about
good and bad people without bringing knowledge into the discussion. Marx did
not solve the social ills of his time; but after Marx it is impossible to
discuss social problems without invoking the classification of society into
classes based on material wealth. What makes these thinkers revolutionary is
that they redirected the discussion and provided a new vocabulary for
exploring, understanding, and seeking to resolve human problems.
The reason these thinkers focus on classification systems directly
is that these systems are never ideologically neutral. The way we organize
things into compartments indicates to us an entire network of relationships and
hierarchies which are loaded with political and moral value. To
take an obvious example. If my moral system requires me to be kind to
human beings, then I must attend to what my classification system tells me
about who is a human being equal to me. If it indicates, as some have done,
that, say, aboriginal people or black people, or the Irish poor are not fully
human, then my moral obligations to them are not the same as my obligations to
the white middle-class people next door. This may be an extreme example, but it
makes the point. And someone who wants me to treat aboriginals, blacks, and the
Irish poor as human beings is never going to persuade me until such time as he
can overthrow my classification system and replace it with a different one.
I want to make you understand Darwin’s achievement in this light.
His work is the culmination of a massive revolution in our classification
systems. If you know anything about the history of biology, you will be
familiar with some of that. But what I want to suggest is that the revolution
he brought about, the classification system which he introduced in biology, has
immediate implications far beyond the question he sets out to investigate, the
origin of species. His masterpiece has only one mention in it of human beings
in it, but the implications of the theory, as Darwin understood only too well,
are direct and overwhelming.
D. The Great Chain of Being
Very simply put, Darwin’s theory is the culmination of a process
which destroyed for ever for us the oldest classification system in our
history, the way in which our culture since the Ancient Greeks had understood
the world. This system was also a biological classification system, the oldest,
most successful and influential system of thinking in our culture: the Great
Chain of Being.
The Great Chain of Being had its origin in Greek philosophy,
particularly in the work of Aristotle. He proposed, as a means of classifying
life, what he called the ladder of life. In this scheme, living things were to
be arranged on an ascending scale, with a particular natural phenomenon’s place
determined by its ability to move. Such a scheme sees life as hierarchically
organized, some forms of life are more primitive than others, some are more fully developed. Hence, in this scheme there
is an applied value judgment.
Aristotle’s ladder of life was appropriated by Christianity in a
combination with a notion from Plato concerning the goodness of God. According
to Plato, if God was perfect, then all forms of life must have been created. To
leave any potential life unrealized would be a violation of the perfection of
the highest power (this idea is called the Principle of Plenitude). Thus, the
Great Chain of Being contained in it all the possible forms of life arranged in
an ordered hierarchy, from the lowest inanimate forms of life, up through the
various stages of plants and animals, then the different ranks of human beings,
from slaves and serfs up to the highest forms of humanity, the kings and queens
and popes, and then up through the various orders of angels (cherubim and
seraphim) right up to God himself. Space itself was organized into the lowest
sphere of imperfection (the area below the moon, that is, the earth and earth’s
atmosphere) and the realm of the perfect heavens (home of the angels and of God
himself).
What’s important to note here is that, although the Great Chain of
Being originated and continued to serve as a biological metaphor, a
classification system, it was very much more than that. This hierarchy linked
everything in the world and beyond to God himself. As an individual part of the
chain, I knew my place: I had a responsibility for the things below me on the
chain and an obligation to those above me. Since the orbits of the planets
coincided with the various orders of angels, the structure of the heavens was
linked directly to the hierarchies of life on earth, and all of creation was a
single coordinated whole. Hence, with this metaphor my understanding of the
world around me and the stars above was inextricably linked to my understanding
of my own purpose in life: science and a moral purpose were fused, and hence
there was no division at all between my religious understanding and my
scientific knowledge.
Thus, the Great Chain of Being served as a religious, moral, and
political metaphor as well as a classification system in natural science. And
this image is so important that it is quite impossible to understand Medieval painting, or Shakespeare’s political vision, or
Renaissance poetic imagery, or Dante’s cosmology without some knowledge of this
vision. It is absolutely fundamental to the way our culture understood itself
for over two thousand years.
It is important to stress two features of this classification
system: first, it was complete. There was no room in it for new life. The
authority for this was Plato’s Principle of Plenitude (that it would be
logically impossible for the highest creative Good not to create everything)
and the Book of Genesis, which states that God created the animal and plant
species in the week of creation. The second important feature was that this
hierarchy was static. It was not a mobile staircase. All life was born into its
particular place in the hierarchy, and living a moral life, being a worthy
animal or person, required one to acknowledge one’s position between higher and
lower forms and to live according to the duties and responsibilities of that
position. The greatest Christian sin was pride, that
is, thinking oneself better than one’s position.
Hence, the political implications of the Great Chain of Being as a
classification system are inherently conservative in the sense that it does not
admit any possibility for change. Kings are superior beings to normal people.
They have a divinely ordained place in the Great Chain of Being which gives
them the responsibility for ruling, just as our position gives us the duty of
obeying. Everyone on the chain is between higher and lower forms, and the
greatest danger to life is to regress to a lower form, especially if that comes
in the attempt to move to a higher level.
Now, the great attraction of the Great Chain of Being, other than
its simplicity and its aesthetically pleasing design as a series of concentric
circles, is that it makes the world morally and physically intelligible. It
tells me who I am, where I belong, and, most important, what I must do. It is a
classification system which links me intimately with all creation and indicates
to me how I ought to live my life. Beyond that, it constantly informs me of God’s
continuing care for me and the world, because in seeing the hierarchies of
being all around me, either in the social structure or in the nature or in the
motions of the planets, I see evidence for his benevolent design. God is
present in the world; I know that because I can see the wonderful design of the
Great Chain of Being everywhere in it.
E. Those Disturbing Astronomers
The first major challenge to the Great Chain of Being came from
the astronomers, who upset the traditional scheme by proposing, with
Copernicus, that the cosmos should have the sun at the centre rather than the
earth. There is not time here to review the stages of this dispute, but I do
want to point out why so many people objected. Everyone has heard about the
trouble Galileo got himself into by seeking to further Copernicus’s model of
the cosmos, and a simplistic criticism is often directed against the inquisitors
as simply power hungry, bigoted, ignorant churchmen. Some of them may have
been. But let me propose something a little more sophisticated. The objection
to Galileo also came from people who recognized what would happen if the Great
Chain of Being classification system was cast aside.
If the universe was really, as Galileo proposed, all simply governed by the
same laws of motion everywhere, without the separate moral spheres, then people’s
understanding of the world might lose much of its moral meaning. They would
cease to be linked so intimately with all elements of creation and with God
himself. In other words, they were objecting to the erosion of morality from
our classification system.
However, for a number of reasons too complex to enter into here,
the trend initiated by Copernicus prevailed and culminated in the publication
of Newton’s Principia, in which he proposed a mathematically accurate
model for understanding the solar system with the sun at one of the focal point
of the elliptical orbits of the planets. But although Newton’s model required a
massive rethinking of the Great Chain of Being, his sun-centred model still
kept the main ingredients of that system vital for three main reasons.
1. First the mathematical precision of Newton’s model seemed to demonstrate beyond doubt that God had organized His creation with a precise design. Hence, we could strengthen our faith in God by contemplating the wonderful mathematical regularity of His creation, as demonstrated by Newton. And throughout the eighteenth century the major defence against the godless revolutionary biologists was an appeal to the divine design demonstrated by Newton.
2. Second, although some of the implications of Newton’s model were disturbing (especially the immense spaces which it required, an unimaginable expansion of the friendly dimensions of traditional astronomy), nothing in it directly contradicted the Genesis account.
3. Thirdly, and as we shall see, most importantly, Newton made no attempt to expand his theory into an account of how the cosmos reached this present arrangement. In fact, he expressly repudiated any mechanical explanation for the development of the heavens. In his view, God had established the heavens in the way Newton’s theory described them, and nothing could possibly alter that other than the direct intervention of God himself. Hence, in Newton’s theory, the structure of the cosmos was as static and divinely ordained as the Great Chain of Being.
F. Static Classification Systems
But the relative stability promised by Newton’s model of the
universe was only one aspect of the challenge to conventional ways of thinking
about the world. For natural scientists looking at plants and animals were
facing something of a crisis during the seventeenth century, a development
brought about by the discovery of new species through overseas exploration,
technical improvements in lenses which led to the discovery of the microscope,
and the growing interest in what we call biology. In 1600, for example, about
6000 plant species had been discovered; by 1700 12,000 more were known. This
was putting enormous pressure on traditional systems of classification.
This rapid proliferation of primary phenomena led in the late
seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries to a marked interest in new
classification systems for plants and animals. Again, there is not time here to
go into the details, but you should know that the this trend culminated in what
has come to be hailed as the first great work of modern biology, something
which has shaped your own studies decisively, that is, the classification
system of the great Swedish natural scientists, Carl Linnaeus. In his System
of Nature, published in 1735, he assigned a descriptive place in a
comprehensive classification system to every known animal and plant. To do
this, he created the binomial system of nomenclature still in use and the
breakdown of the organic structures into Classes, Orders, Genera, Species, and
Varieties.
Linnaeus, however, did not break with the tradition of the Great
Chain of Being. For him, species were fixed and eternal. There was no such
thing as a new species. He thus saw his descriptive classification not as a
human construct fixing the stages of a developing nature but as defining
categories established by God at the time of creation. Linnaeus’s account of
nature, therefore, reinforced and, as it were, updated the traditional
hierarchical, static understanding of nature.
G. The Design Argument
By the end of the seventeenth century and the early eighteenth
century, there was a widespread feeling that in the work of Newton the new
natural science and religion had been very happily reconciled. The evidence for
an elaborate and pleasing design in the universe had been demonstrated by
Newton, and such a design for many people clearly demonstrated the existence of
a designer, a divine mathematician, without whose active shaping intelligence
no such design would have been possible. Linnaeus’s work (which was far less
well known) had suggested a similar carefully ordered structure for organic
beings.
This design argument is vital to understand. Modern science, on
the Newtonian model, explained natural phenomena on mechanical principles. That
is, it focused on how things work, using mechanical
models and mathematical formula (the standard image was that of the universe
operating like a perfect clock). It does not take into account any sense of
moral purpose (which was the basis of the old science). In fact, modern science
had started in the work of Galileo and Bacon, among others, with the insistence
that secondary causes (the mechanical processes of cause and effect) were the
true work of the natural scientist and that first causes (the moral
understanding of the purposes of things) should not enter into scientific
explanations.
In that sense, science could be seen as being hostile to religion:
it divorced explanations of natural things from moral or divine purposes.
However, the design argument could overcome this problem. If the mechanical
model demonstrated some evidence of intricate and regular design, then, so the
design argument held, there must have been a designer. Hence, the mathematical
regularity of nature, especially Newton’s cosmology, could be used to reinforce
religious belief. Thus, science was actively encouraged and carried on by
devout Christians and many practising clergy as the most important way to
promote religious faith. It is quite wrong to think, as many naively assume,
that science and religion were natural enemies. That is very far from the case.
H. Historical Science
But even as many people were celebrating the triumph of natural
science as the handmaiden of religion, forces were at work which were to
challenge this design argument and, in the culminating experience of Darwin’s
work, to overthrow, not just the union between science and religion but also,
in many people’s minds, religion itself. That development we call historical
science.
The term historical science introduces a new form of understanding
phenomena. It refers to the method of seeking to understand a natural
phenomenon, not with reference to an eternally fixed classification system (on
the model of Linnaean or Newtonian systems), something ordained by God from
time immemorial, but rather with reference to a story. A historical approach to
explaining something seeks to claim that we can best understand something by
describing its origin, development, and perhaps its future direction.
The development of historical thinking has a revolutionary impact
for one vital reason: by suggesting that something has a story and is not
eternally fixed in the form we now find it, the thinker is implicitly denying
the possibility that the phenomenon has an eternal stability or, indeed, any stability.
Once I start thinking of things as having a history, then I have to deal with
the fact that once they were not as they are now and presumably they will not
be as they are now at some point in the future. What they are now is simply one
stage of an ongoing process. Historical thinking thus tends to undercut all
claims to the eternal rightness of anything. Whatever is understood
historically potentially has no essence. It is not essentially anything
specific, only a series of changes. Or, putting the matter philosophically, a
historical way of looking at things suggests that there is not
such thing as permanent being, there is only an uninterrupted process of
becoming.
The political and religious implications of this form of thinking
cannot be overestimated. Let me take one example. If I believe in the Great
Chain of Being, in the eternally fixed divinely ordained classification system
which has arranged things hierarchically, then I will be a strong supporter of
the system of government based upon the traditional classes and ways of doing
business. That, after all, is ordained by God and is a law of nature. If, on
the other hand, I develop a historical imagination, then the present
arrangement is not something permanent, not something eternally underwritten by
a Law of God. It is the product of a process. Thus, it can and will be changed.
It is going somewhere. Hence, my attitude towards the distribution of power,
the value of different parts of the system, and so on will change. These are
only temporary stages in the historical development of the state, not eternally
valid.
Historical science began gradually and was fiercely resisted. I
shall be mentioning some features of that development and resistance in a
moment. But it is very important to grasp the revolutionary potential of this
form of thinking. We are so used to it, that we take it for granted, so that it
is difficult for us to imagine a different form of thinking. The fact is,
however, that until very recent times, people in western culture, like so many
other people in other cultures, have thought of the past and the present as
essentially the same. The forces which govern us, divine and secular, are not
subject to a progressive process but are permanent features of human life.
I. The Geologists
And why at this time did historical thinking begin to invade our
thinking? The answer to that comes from the rising study of the earth carried
on by natural scientists looking closely at the earth (we would now call them
geologists). And why were people starting to thinking in a new way about the
earth? Well, one reason is that all over Europe in the eighteenth and early
nineteenth centuries people were digging canals and
building big new cities, and there was growing pressure to come up with some explanations
for the curious observations people were starting to make everywhere as they
probed the surface layers of the earth.
Again, this is a complex subject, but the geologists put onto the
table three problems which were very difficult to account for by customary
accounts of the creation of the Earth in Genesis or by static classification
systems:
1. First, there was the clear evidence of layering in the sedimentary strata of the earth. This strongly suggested two things: (a) that much of the earth now dry land had been formed under water and (b) that there had been a succession of inundations (rather than just a single one).
2. Second, and most important, there was the thorny problem of fossils. How did fossils of sea creatures get into the rocks at the highest elevations? How come many of these fossils had little to no resemblance to known animal and plant species on earth today? Why in many layers were there no human fossils? How could one explain the growing evidence that a number of species seem to have disappeared, to have become extinct?
3. Third, the earth was clearly changing. Under the forces of erosion, of alluvial deposits (e.g., at river deltas), of volcanic eruptions, and so on, even in historical time things were rapidly altering. Cities once at the edge of the sea were now miles inland; certain villages in Egypt were now buried in the sand. The Nile Delta had clearly changed. How could such environmental changes be reconciled with a static, eternally unchanging view of the natural world, especially since it was clear that there had always been a close connection between environmental conditions and the sustenance of animal and plant life?
As a result of these (and other) questions, a new form of scientific
work began to appear, a theory of the earth. These were explanations for how
the world had acquired the features the geologists were describing. And such
explanations required a narrative, a story, a historical explanation. Such
questions could not easily be answered with an eternal mechanical model like
Newton’s vision of the heavens. The only way to deal with them was to explain
how the earth had once been very different and for some reason had changed and
was still changing.
J. The Book of Genesis
Now, a major difficulty here is that Western Christianity is based
upon a historical explanation for the creation of the earth and everything in
it. The Book of Genesis, in traditional Christian belief, is a historical
account. It was not just a convenient myth but a true story of God’s creation.
And the same is true for the story of the flood.
Hence, the first efforts of British geology, in fact one of the
first books of modern geology, was written by an Anglican bishop in an attempt
to reconcile the Genesis account with mechanical science. Burnet’s The
Sacred Theory of the Earth (1680-1690) is often maligned as too fanciful
and unempirical. By modern standards the science was crude, but the attempt was
an honest one, for Burnet insisted that defenders of religion must not fight
the new science; it was essential that the two be reconciled. And God would not
have given human beings a scientific understanding if the two could not be
reconciled.
His effort was followed by many others. In fact, publishing theories
of the earth became a major literary genre, and the number of competing
theories proliferated to the point where it was difficult to keep track of
them. This is one of the great anarchic periods of modern science. Unlike
today, there were no institutionalized authorities to rule on what might count
as a viable theory and what might not; there was no agreed upon method for what
characterized the activity known as natural science. So the richness and
variety of scientific theories and the rapidly accumulating empirical data make
this one of the most fascinating and exciting periods in the history of
science.
Gradually, however, three tendencies emerged, as in all
revolutionary situations. There was the old guard, those who wanted to hang
onto the traditional notions at all costs. These were natural scientists who
strove to maintain the fixity of species, the unchanging nature of the earth, the denial of a historical development over time. At the
other extreme were those with a growing interest in historical development
without regard to traditional views of the Book of Genesis. These people were
increasingly flirting with the idea of some evolutionary development, that is,
the development of new species out of the transformation of old species by some
as yet unknown process (such ideas were growing increasingly common by the
second half of the eighteenth century). In the middle were the moderates: those
who were growing increasingly convinced of some historical development but who
strove to reconcile such an account with traditional religion and with
interpretations of the Genesis account.
K. The Political and Religious Dimensions of this Scientific
Conflict
None of the major players in these disputes carried on his work in
isolation from a host of non-scientific questions, for the political and
religious implications of scientific theories were of major concern. To defend
the fixity of species and the lack of a historical development was, obviously
enough, to insist on an agenda of traditional stability. If the classification
systems of nature were eternally fixed in accordance with known compartments or
laws, then it was wrong to talk about developmental change. By contrast, to
talk of historical development was to undermine the legitimacy of the present order
of things; it was to suggest very strongly that change in the biological world
might endorse change in the political world.
What made these debates all the more vital in the second half of
the eighteenth century and well into the nineteenth was that Europe was going
through another crisis, and a biological one at that.
The population was exploding. In fifty years the population of Europe doubled;
then it doubled again; and then it doubled again. Under the pressure of the
industrial revolution huge new cities were developing. Communities which had
been sleepy agricultural villages became huge industrial cities in a
generation. Everyone could see around them what was happening, but lacking any
statistical or census data, no one could understand the full dimensions of the
problem, and no one knew why this was happening (historians are still debating
the causes).
As a result of this enormous demographic dislocation poverty was
becoming a massive problem and a new social threat was clearly developing: the urban
mob, massive numbers of anonymous, frequently rebellious, chronically poor and
hungry, often transient citizens. Throughout the late eighteenth century and
the early nineteenth century the political tensions of this transformation of
European society were everywhere.
The pressure to introduce political reforms was increasingly
urgent. And scientific theories were introduced and measured against this
political agenda. Theories suggesting historical change as the basis for
science were, as one might expect, welcomed by the reformers; theories denying
the validity of historical change were, as one might expect, endorsed by
conservatives. Hence, concepts of evolution of some kind attracted a following
among radical and reform circles (Charles Darwin’s grandfather, Erasmus Darwin,
was an early advocate).
The climate changed dramatically in 1789, with the outbreak of the
French revolution, in which the urban masses overthrew the old order, massacred
the royal family and set up a republican government. This created an enormous
panic among other European states and made any proposals for change immediately
suspect. Hence, scientific theories which were quite acceptable among reforming
circles before 1789 became treasonous afterwards. The growing interest in evolution
became associated with godless French science, and anyone advocating it could
bid farewell to a professional career as a natural scientist, doctor, or
teacher. The extraordinarily hostile climate for historical biology in the
years in which Darwin was growing up can only be understood in the context of
this political climate.
L. Evolution
And yet in the one hundred years before the publication of Darwin’s
book the evidence for some form of evolution was becoming overwhelming. The
argument in support of this concept is very simple and totally persuasive. Let
me review it for you.
The case for evolution begins with an obvious truth which no sane
person can deny, namely, that there is variety in the animal and plant world.
The second point in the argument is that all living creatures must have a
living parent. This was by no means clear in the eighteenth century (the
question was not finally resolved until Louis Pasteur, the great
nineteenth-century French biologist, solved the problem of fermentation),
but increasing numbers of people were ceasing to believe in spontaneous
generation of life from non-life (one of the most ancient beliefs going right
back to ancient times). The third point establishing the truth of evolution was
the growing evidence that some animals had existed on earth long before the
present animal population. The conclusion to this argument was inescapable: the
later animals must have developed out of the earlier animals, with some
significant morphological change (i.e., evolution). No question was more vital
in the arguments about evolution than fossils, and it was becoming increasingly
difficult to maintain the idea of the eternal fixity of species in light of all
the bones people were digging out of the earth.
And so the conservative anti-evolutionary forces changed shifted
their ground and began interpreting Genesis as something not entirely literal.
Yes, indeed, there had been different ages to the earth. The Genesis account
was the story of the last of these changes, and the days of creation should not
be considered literally. They were different time spans. Such a view enabled
people to account for the evidence for extinction and for the successive
layering of the rock strata of the earth without making any concessions to evolution.
The history of the earth is thus a history of God’s successive interventions,
which constituted a series of disasters, Noah’s Flood being the last in the
series. These theories are now given the general name of Catastrophe Theories
or Catastrophism.
Opposing the Catastrophists were a group with a growing interest
in what has become a fundamental principle of modern historical science,
something I am sure you all subscribe to, although you may not be aware of it.
This is the principle of uniformitarianism, the key
assumption that we can only deal with a scientific narrative by assuming that
the forces at work in the world around us today are exactly the same as the
forces which have always been at work. Moreover, these forces have always operated
at the same rate. Hence, the chief business of historical science,
that is, accounting for the process of earth and the development of life,
must begin by explaining everything in terms of present processes.
The uniformitarians had one huge problem
to overcome, namely the issue of time. It took no great knowledge of natural
processes to realize that if existing land forms, like, say, the Grand Canyon,
had been produced by the same processes as we could now observe, then these
processes must have been going on for millions and millions of years, for a
length of time almost inconceivable in a culture which had always been used to
thinking of the age of the earth in terms of thousands of years (this was and
still remains an important objection to Darwin’s account). One of the great
advantages of Catastrophism was that it could remove
this difficulty by arguing for sudden, inexplicable and divinely ordained,
catastrophic interventions. The problem for them, of course, was explaining
such processes.
A key figure in the Catastrophist cause was the great French
palaeontologist Georges Cuvier in the early nineteenth century. No one did more
than he did to link the classification of fossils to the different rock strata
and to insist that the real business of biology was comparative anatomy linked
to geology, so that we could gain an accurate understanding of the temporal
sequence of species. But Cuvier adamantly opposed evolution and argued strongly
against setting any enormous length of time for the present development of the
earth. There was, he argued, no evidence for either, and it was impossible for
gradual change to occur because an animal was such a highly organized complex
interconnection that any change in one part would require the immediate transformation
of all other parts. Looking at the present state of the earth, Cuvier concluded
that the last great catastrophe must have taken place about 5000 years ago, a
time very close to the time indicated by Genesis for Noah’s Flood.
M. Containing Evolution
As the evidence for evolution accumulated (largely through fossils
and a growing understanding of the layers of the earth), traditional opponents
made concessions to the idea. Two prominent strategies for holding the full
implications of evolution at bay emerged.
The first was to concede that the earth was subject to constant
change and was not static, but to propose that the change was cyclical. Thus,
there was a permanent unchanging pattern by which the earth worked, and the
changes we could see were like the orbits of the planets, phases in an
eternally recurring cycle. Of course, the time periods were immensely longer
than for the planetary orbits, but essentially there was a constant pattern.
This idea informs the first great work of British geology, James Hutton’s Theory
of the Earth, in which he proposed the rock cycle, a process by which rocks
were eroded, broken down, and carried off into the sea where they formed
sedimentary layers. Under pressure and heat in the depths the rocks reformed
and emerged from the molten material to form new rocks and thus to complete the
cycle. Hence, there was, amid the change, an eternal permanence in the pattern
of the cycle.
The second strategy to contain evolution was to concede that some
species change was possible, but that it was limited within groups. Thus, while
there might be some development in the group of, say, mammals, there was no
movement from one major group to another (e.g., from reptiles to mammals).
Thus, evolution is a limited phenomenon and not the ruling principle of nature.
[This latter position, a favourite of conservative biologists by
the end of the 18th century was challenged seriously by the arrival
on the scene of a duck-billed platypus, which seemed a new species clearly
intermediate between reptiles and mammals and which was hailed by the radical
biologists as evidence for a thoroughgoing evolutionary principle across major
divisions. A furious intellectual, anatomical, religious, and political fight
ensued (with the Royal Navy under orders to keep the supply of specimens, all
from Australia, out of the hands of French scientists). It concluded with a
victory for the conservatives, led by Owen, the well known British anatomist
who classified the species as a variety of mammal. The establishment was so
delighted with Owen’s work in this fight against the
French that they promoted him to the Royal Society].
A third strategy to contain evolution was to see it guided by
divine processes and thus quite reconcilable with religious feeling (although
not, perhaps, with Genesis). Hence, change was a progressive manifestation of
God’s love for humanity. This idea could easily be adapted to secular visions
of progress without the guiding presence of God (for example, by seeing in the
history of life a progressive moral improvement in animal life, a direction
aiming at a much higher form over time).
N. Lamarck
It was a colleague of Cuvier’s, Jean-Baptiste
Lamarck, who first put on the table a full blown scientific theory of evolution
in 1809. Lamarck endorsed the hierarchy of being, the scale of nature, but for
him it was a moving and progressive hierarchy. Organic forms could produce
significantly different offspring by developing in themselves different
characteristics. The driving agent of morphological change was the environment
and habit (something Erasmus Darwin had also proposed). The divisions
biologists had created to divide off one species from another were, Lamarck
proposed, arbitrary aids to memory, not eternally fixed divinely ordained categories.
To demonstrate this, Lamarck paid great attention to invertebrates, pointing
out that there were not nearly enough categories for them in existing systems
of classification and proposing the addition of a number of new categories
(multiplying the categories significantly reduces the differences between those
animals on the ends of the classification system and puts pressure on the
biologist to see how one species could merge or run into another). For Lamarck
evolution was progressive (leading to better forms of life) and could be
restarted at any time, since he believed in spontaneous generation of life from
non-living matter.
Lamarck’s theory received a very hostile reception, especially in
England. Conservatives everywhere, including his eminent colleague Cuvier
derided him. He died in obscurity and poverty, and history has been unkind to
him by forgetting the boldness of his evolutionary scheme and castigating him
for his enthusiastic endorsement of the inheritance of acquired characteristics
(something Darwin also subscribed to). Even Darwin, normally a polite
controversialist, seems to have slighted Lamarck. But Lamarck deserves an
honoured place in the history of biology (a term he invented), and if as a
result of this talk some of you become a little curious about reading what he
had to say, then this talk will have achieved something important.
O. Darwin
At this stage you might well be starting to ask yourself what was
so special about Darwin. If evolution had been around in some form or another
for about one hundred years before Darwin, and if Lamarck had published a fully
fledged comprehensive theory of evolution fifty years before the publication of
Origin of Species, then why was Darwin such a revolutionary? It’s clear
the effect of his work does not depend on a new theory of inheritance (Darwin’s
notion of inheritance was a grave defect in his theory, since the “blending”
process he proposed would have made his theory impossible), and he subscribed
as firmly to the inheritance of acquired characteristics as Lamarck. So what
was the big deal? He offered no major new discoveries of amazing species or
fossils (as Cuvier had done), so why is he considered such a vital
contribution?
Darwin’s importance comes from this central idea: the process
which drives evolution is essentially random and linear. In Darwin’s theory,
variations are produced by some as yet unknown process, and life is preserved
or goes under on the simple and brutal principle of survival of the fittest.
The development of particular forms of life in all its forms (including human
life) is thus to be understood, not as evidence of divine design, but as the
accidental by-products of a process that never had them in mind in the first place.
And this holds for human beings as much as for anyone else. Moreover, there is
no eternal recurrence in the process. We don’t know where we are going, but we
do know that we are not going to be coming back. Evolution goes in one random
direction only, and extinction is forever.
Darwin’s account is absolutely devastating because it shatters the
design argument and thus irreparably severs the understanding of life
scientifically from any sense of moral purpose. The narrative of life is not
merely contrary to Genesis in the sense that species are not fixed and that
immense lengths of time are required (these had been on the table for some
time), but because God has no place in the business. The process is a chance
encounter between variations and environmental conditions. Pushed to its
extreme in the language of the modern ultra-Darwinist Dawkins: human beings are
nothing more than survival sites for DNA. Simply put, Darwin’s theory buried
one of the oldest and most vital hopes which human beings had used to sustain
themselves: that the richly patterned world around them was the best evidence
of some higher purpose at work in our lives.
Philosophers had prepared the groundwork for getting rid of the
design argument before Darwin (although not with empirical evidence but on
logical grounds), pointing out that it was impossible to make non-physical (or
metaphysical) conclusions about God on the basis of physical evidence. But few
people, other than professional philosophers, read Hume or Kant with any understanding.
And a standard popular response to them was the evidence of design provided by
Newton’s cosmology or the marvelous evidence of functioning design in nature
(in, for example, something like the eye). Darwin’s book made it crystal clear.
Nature provided evidence, not of God, but of a brutal irrational struggle
governed by chance in which the penalty for loss was extinction for ever and the reward only a temporary stage until the
species changed under the pressure of environmental conditions. The amazing
structure of the eye was no evidence for design; it was simply a functioning
tool shaped gradually under the mechanical random imperatives of natural
selection. And soon enough (in evolutionary time) it would change into
something else.
And there was no particular direction to the change. It is not the
case that evolution is going anywhere (this is a big difference between Lamarck
and Darwin). Animal and plant life is not getting better in any moral sense;
there is no divine plan at work in the histories we construct. There is only
change.
P. The Immediate Effect of Darwin’s Idea
In Darwin’s own time, the full impact of his ideas had relatively
little effect (although his book was very popular)--other than working to get
the concept of evolution more widely accepted. He added persuasive weight to
the evidence for evolution, but his idea of natural selection as the driving
mechanism of evolution was not immediately adopted either by the scientific
community or by anyone else. The main reason for this was scientific: there
were too many unexplained problems with what he was proposing.
The main problem Darwin’s theory faced was that there was no
comprehensible theory of inheritance which would make the theory work. Darwin’s
own theory of inheritance, that the sexual material of both
parents “blended” in the
offspring, was clearly inadequate, because (as the Scottish engineer
Jenkins pointed out) it made the theory unworkable. Any advantageous variation
which suddenly appeared would not last; it would simply be blended away in the
general population, and thus species change would be impossible.
A second objection (still heard today) concerns the length of time
necessary for the process Darwin was proposing. The best estimates of the
eminent physics community placed the age of the earth as far younger than
Darwin’s theory demanded. These estimates were based upon measurements of the
rate of the earth’s cooling. Since at the time no one knew anything about
radioactivity, it seemed quite impossible that the earth could have been
sustaining life for such a long time without having long ago lost all its heat.
The third objection (still at the heart of debates about Darwin)
concerns the lack of transitional types. Darwin admitted this problem and dealt
with it by referring the reader to the future discoveries of more fossils. This
has taken place, and thousands of intermediate types have been found, although
not in the numbers and sequences that Darwin’s theory seems to demand.
And there were major objections to Darwin’s method. He was
proposing to explain something which he could not directly observe (obviously
so, since evolution of one species into another takes far too long). So he
formulated a hypothesis, without no direct evidence of
the process he was explaining, and hoped that the explanatory power of the
theory would make up for the lack of any direct observational evidence. Today
this method (called the hypothetico-deductive method)
is standard; but in Darwin’s time, when many scientists demanded (in the tradition
launched by Bacon) that science must always have a firm empirical base, his
method of arguing seemed suspiciously unscientific.
So Darwin’s immediate reputation never in his own lifetime reached
the heights which Newton had achieved instantly with the publication of his
masterpiece one hundred years before. By a curious irony, the essential theory
of heredity which would have rendered his theory instantly more plausible was,
in fact, developed within seven years of the publication of Darwin’s book. But
the theory was published in a remote part of Eastern Europe by an Augustian monk, Gregor Mendel, and no one made the
connection because no one knew about Mendel’s work. So the emergence of Darwin’s
theory of natural selection had to wait for widespread acceptance until Mendel’s
experiments were rediscovered and the great marriage between Darwin’s theory of
natural selection and Mendelian genetics took place
in the first third of this century.
Q. Some Long-Term Effects of This Proposal
I take it that the immediate consequences of Darwin’s theory are
clear enough from what I have already said above about the design argument, but
I would like to dwell on some of the more complex long-term views. The most
fundamental consequence is the following: If we take Darwin’s concept and
develop it fully, then what is destroyed is the traditional concept of truth
and the search for the truth becomes a vain endeavour. Just as in Darwin’s
theory, the term species loses any permanent definable meaning which might
survive time, so any term ceases to have lasting meaning and the search for
such terms becomes a denial of how the world works. This statement requires
some elaboration.
Since the time of the Ancient Greeks the aim of knowledge had been
to discover the truth, not simply about the natural world, but about human
beings and their natures. There was a basic assumption that there was such a
thing as truth and that human beings could find out enough about it to orient
themselves properly towards it. The major arguments were about the appropriate
method for getting to it. For example, to cite a very common tension: should we
use reason as our guide (as Plato had insisted) or should we use the revealed
word of God (as many Christian theologians had insisted) or should we find some
appropriate combination of both. Modern science was launched in the seventeenth
century as a part of this quest.
What did these people mean by truth? They meant an eternal
unchanging permanently defined order to the word, a means of understanding the
obvious flux and process of experience in terms of something eternally the
same. In philosophical language they were looking for something essential, not
something which was just one stage in a process of becoming. Behind the demand
for a belief in the fixity of species, for example, was the desire to see in
biological classification systems that eternal sense of order, that permanent
defining essence of the natural world.
Even when people recognized that the world is in constant process,
the truth could lie in some permanent definition or some equation of the
process. For many people, this is what Newton seems to have delivered. The
cosmos might be in constant motion, but there was an eternally true set of equations
which defined that motion. James Hutton’s work in geology was an attempt to set
earth science on the same footing. And Kant’s historicizing of Newton’s vision
of the universe did exactly the same (the universe might be changing, but the
change is cyclical and eternal renewal is the divine pattern in the process).
Darwin, in many peoples
eyes, destroyed this possibility. It is obvious enough on the level of animal
life. If species and variations are constantly being produced and selected by a
random process, then nothing has a true definition because nothing stays the
same. All definitions are temporary conveniences we use for descriptive
purposes. As Nietzsche observed, “Only that which has no history can be
defined.” Darwin is saying, in effect, all human life is only its history; that
is how we must understand it. Therefore nothing can be eternally and
permanently defined, and hence we can never know the truth of any form of life:
we can only know its present stage and its past genealogy (in fact reconstructing
genealogies becomes a major task in biology).
This point is clear enough if one reflects momentarily on the word
species. For the Greeks and traditional scientists, this word had an
important meaning: a species was an eternally fixed category of creation. When
we defined species or studied them, we were thus dealing with the reality of
things, the truth of nature. But for Darwin (and other historical biologists)
the term species is simply a convenient and temporary label for
something that was not there (or was very different) in the past and which will
disappear or change fundamentally in the future. Hence, the very idea of species
loses its claim to represent the eternal reality of nature, the truth.
Once this idea gets applied to social structures and moral systems
the effects are devastating. If it makes sense to talk about the random
evolution of animal and plant life, why cannot we do the same with human
societies and systems of knowledge? Put another way: Darwin had said that in order
to understand life we must construct a genealogy (a family tree) tracing a
constant record of change; this would indicate the path taken but would reveal
nothing other than successful adaptation (which has nothing to do with merit or
progress and everything to do with luck). And such a family record would
provide no reliable indication of the future, other than the virtual certainty
that we would significantly change or die out forever.
Well, why should we not come to understand our political system in
the same way, as merely a genealogy without higher purpose, the product of
variation and survival in a different arena. What if
we apply this thinking even to language itself, the means by which we formulate
our understanding of the truth? If our languages are, like living organisms,
always in process of change under the accidental pressures of historical
events, then nothing we say can be permanently true.
Darwin’s theory thus gave a powerful revolutionary impetus to the
development of modern thought, particularly to those who wish to deny the
particular lasting “rightness” of any system of belief. Systems of belief are
like organic structures; if they enable people and groups of people to survive
for a while then they are “true” for the period of time and for those people
for whom they work. They will be inevitably replaced or disappear as
circumstances change and they lose their effectiveness. All human thought is,
like animal and plant structures, basically pragmatic. We adopt it and value
it, not because it’s true but because, at this particular moment of time in
these particular circumstances, it works. We pass it on for its survival value
in the full knowledge that in a changed system of the world it will be replaced
by some new “truth” which will, in fact, be no more true
than the old one but which will be more effective for survival. And this
succession of changes is not a progress, because we are not going anywhere, or
getting better in any meaningful sense of the term. We are simply changing as the
chance changes in our genes and our environment dictate.
John Dewey, the great American philosopher much influenced by
Darwin, made the point clearly. There are two ways of comprehending the changes
we see taking place all around us in the natural, social, and political world.
We can seek to explain them in terms of some eternally unchanging essence (a
god or a mathematical formula), so that the change becomes a manifestation of
an underlying permanence. Or we can accept the change as change and deny the
existence of some guiding transcendent principle. If we accept the latter, then
it is pointless to seek to understand the world as eternally anything;
understanding the world becomes a matter of constructing a narrative. The only
thing we can truly know is how we got here, not what it means in the light of
anything lasting. The incentive for the latter form of thinking, Dewey
attributed, quite correctly, to Darwin. Dewey points out that Darwin did not
act alone, of course, but, as I mentioned at the start, his theory is the
devastating culmination of a long line of enquiry.
Now, I’m not saying that everyone was or has been converted. By no means. But Darwin put all sorts of traditional claims
about the truth or religion or the lasting truth of any claim on the defensive;
if one could trace the genesis, development, and evolution of the claim (in
other words, if one could establish a genealogy for the idea), then, like an
animal species, its present incarnation was merely a stage in the process.
Revolutionary thinkers were quick to draw these consequences from Origin of
Species and to launch energetic attacks on all claims to an enduring truth
for political, moral, or social systems. Their argument essentially was this:
the world has no preordained form, in a sense, the world is not anything fixed;
the world is history of accidental changes.
By a powerful irony, this form of thinking has in recent decades
been turned against science itself. Many people claim that science, too, just
like all other systems, is not true, nor is it on the path to truth. It is
simply an accidentally evolved means of coping with the world which we have
adopted to meet a particular contingent set of historical circumstances and
which we will abandon when we need something better. We do not know more about
the world than we knew one thousand years ago; we have simply changed the tools
which we use to cope with life. Science has no more claim
to be the truth of anything than has any other artificial system of belief,
poetic or religion. Science is just one more pragmatic fiction.
I know of very few scientists who subscribe to this idea (and I do
not subscribe to it myself), but the authority for it rests as much on Darwin’s
views of life as on anything else. In my judgment, the best answer to these
disturbing implications of Darwin’s theory is the view that science is not just
a survival strategy for the moment, but is in fact moving closer to the truth
of things (or, more accurately put, to accurate approximations to and models of
that truth), so that the quest for certainty is not something we have to
abandon (but that is the subject of another lecture).
Thus, in order to come back to the place where I started, it will
be easier for you to understand why there is still such resistance to Darwin’s
ideas. I think it is very difficult for people, scientists as well as others,
to hold onto a vision of life which empties life of any higher purpose,
progressive development, or permanent standards of any kind. It’s not just the
case that evolution contradicts the book of Genesis. After all, evolution can
be, and has been, reconciled with religious views. One simply has to see some
divine pattern in the genealogy or some divine purpose a work (one unknown to
us, perhaps). Nor is it the immense time spans which Darwin’s theory requires
(as uncomfortable as these may be). The key idea is the lack of purpose, the
randomness, the emphasis on a directionless but irreversible development
responding to the accidental changes in the environment. To anyone who wants to
think of his or her life having more than a simple mechanical purpose linked to
the temporary survival of the particular variations their body represents, such
a notion is impossible to accept in full, unless one is prepared to place it in
the wider context of a religious belief which the theory neither demands nor
supports.
That many people still find this very uncomfortable (as they
should) is revealed, in part, by the continuing popularity of the design
argument (now usually called Intelligent Design). If you are unfamiliar with
this concept, simply try and Internet search under that label, and stand back
for a tidal wave of results.
As I mentioned at the start, I believe Darwin himself had a strong
sense of these implications of his theory, and they bothered him. Given the
strong religious views of his family, especially his wife, and his own
moderately progressive political inclinations and generally equitable
temperament, it would be very unlikely if he had not been deeply concerned. So one can understand his sickness and his long delay in
publishing. But he was a true scientist and did not shrink from the
implications of the enquiry he had set out upon such a long time before. We
all, biologists and Liberal Studies teachers, have to live with the
consequences.
I began this lecture by mentioning that many people in North
America flatly refuse to accept Darwin’s ideas. As a final footnote to this
cursory discussion, one might observe that there is a Darwinian explanation for
the refusal to accept Darwin. Given the very pessimistic conclusions about
moral purpose to which his theory drives us, and given the importance of a
sense of moral purpose in helping us cope with life, a refusal to believe
Darwin’s theory may have important survival value.