Lecture on Kant’s “Perpetual
Peace”
[The following is the text of a short lecture
delivered in Liberal Studies 401 at Malaspina
University College (now Vancouver Island University) by Ian Johnston. This
document is in the public domain, released June 1999]
For comments or questions, please
contact Ian Johnston
Near the end of his essay “Perpetual Peace” Kant squarely
addresses a question that we ought to be thoroughly familiar with by now,
because it is almost certainly the most frequent issue we have discussed from
one text to another in Liberal Studies. And that is question of the
relationship between practical political behaviour and morality, between how
people do behave in politics and how they ought to behave.
Any observer of political action recognizes almost immediately
that political action, as it actually occurs, is often, perhaps even usually, a
morally questionable business (deception, lying, cruelty, self-interest). At
the same time most of us have a sense that political behaviour could and should
be better than it is. Politicians, we hold, should subject their actions and
decisions to some form of moral control.
This is the ancient conflict between what the Greeks called Kratos (Political Force) and Ethos (moral behaviour)--and
there is no other issue which we have put on the table more frequently than
this one. Before addressing Kant’s remarks, then, I’d like to review some of
the formulations. I’m doing this by way of an introduction to the seminar
discussions this afternoon, which can address in greater detail Kant’s
contributions to this on going debate.
Many months ago, at the start of LBST 301, we read the Odyssey.
At the conclusion of that story we see Odysseus in disguise carry out a
ferocious revenge on the suitors and their supporters--an action which involves
killing, cruelty, deception, lies, and courage and which is effective in
restoring him to the throne of Ithaka. Homer does not
raise political questions directly, but the story puts great pressure on the
readers to explore the extent to which Odysseus’ effective use of force is
justified, is, in other words, an acceptable moral act. And the structure of
the narrative leads most of us to accept that what he does is just because the
suitors have violated the most important moral rules of that world, the
sanctity of the home--a rule which the gods themselves have repeatedly endorsed
throughout the poem.
In this case, the suitors have behaved in a recognizably normal
way: out of self-interest, ambition, power. And they have justified what they
do by an appeal to their own power: What are you going to do about it? We
recognize, too, that, in the context of the story they are morally wrong,
because the guardians of moral order in the world of the Odyssey, the
gods, tell us repeatedly that the suitors ought not to act that way. So when
Odysseus carries out forcefully his revenge, we recognize that as a morally
justified political act. What makes it a moral act is that it is in accordance
with the principles of moral order which govern the Odyssey (we may
disagree with those principles, but in the context of the text it seems clear
that what Odysseus is doing is good).
The same is true about the Lord’s treatment of the Egyptian
Pharaoh. Once again, we questioned and debated the fairness of God’s extremely
forceful punishment of the Egyptians, but the text encourages us to see that
Pharaoh’s political behaviour is immoral and therefore his forceful punishment
is deserved.
The Oresteia obviously
makes this question of the just use of political power the central issue in the
trilogy. In fact, the resolution of that work strongly suggests that a new
organization in the polis--an assembly of citizens responsible for matters of
justice--will foster a better union of political force and moral behaviour and
keep in check a system of egocentric slaughter of the sort manifested by
Agamemnon’s treatment of Troy and Clytaemnestra’s
treatment of Agamemnon and Cassandra.
I mention these stories because they were our first introduction
in Liberal Studies to the need to evaluate the use of political force in the
context of a moral sense of right and wrong. Put another way, we can say that
we all acknowledge that running a human society always requires the effective
use of practical force in all sorts of ways; but we also acknowledge that there
are right and wrong ways to apply this force, that political force, in itself,
is not necessarily good or bad. However, it needs to be guided by some sense of
morality if we are to have any sense of Justice.
Over the past months we have looked at a number of texts which
have explored this issue. Plato, as we saw, made the balance between Ethos and Kratos central to the Republic, and saw the best
hope for a meaningful combination in the education of an elite group of rulers.
These people, since they most fully understood the nature of the good (of right
and wrong) would have all the power, so that their political decisions would
therefore always be just. Their understanding of moral issues is essential if
the force entrusted to them is to be used justly.
It’s important to notice that Plato is not in the Republic undertaking
an analysis of how human beings actually do behave in the modern political
arena (although he does often remark on that behaviour). He is focusing above
all on what ought to be the case, on what a fully moral politics would be. And,
as we saw, he bases his main moral argument on the belief that some people are
capable of achieving full moral development through a specialized education (at
least in a thought experiment they are; his hopes that such a program as the Republic
outlines is at all practical are far more pessimistic). To those people,
his thought experiment concludes, we ought to entrust the power, since they
will be the only ones who understand how to use that power morally so as to
ensure justice. Anyone else will abuse the power entrusted to him.
Aristotle, like Plato, believed that virtue in the rulers was the
best guarantee of justice in the state, but he differed from Plato in how he
thought such virtue might be best encouraged and developed so that power in the
state was exercised with an appropriate sense of morality. And the Christian
tradition, which relied heavily on Plato and especially Aristotle for its
thinking about politics, generally agreed that virtue in the ruler, the
responsibility of his or her Church educators and advisors, was the surest way
to achieve the just use of political force. Hence, justice in the state (the
moral use of power) depended above all upon the education of the ruler.
In each of these examples, the education of the person with the
force is central, and there is an institutional arrangement to bring about that
education: in Plato it is a complex and radically new system of schooling, in
the Aristotelian tradition and in the Christian tradition the Church based upon
it, the emphasis is much more on tradition. Whether we are talking about a
utopian possibility or a practical reform, these thinkers see that society must
provide for putting power in the hands of the most virtuous (or, conversely,
making those with the power fully virtuous).
The most decisive break with this ancient tradition of virtue
comes in Machiavelli’s The Prince. For he spends most of his time making
the case that if the Prince concentrates on learning about the practical
effectiveness of force (of Kratos) then the Prince’s
virtue can be left out of account. I tried to make the case in the lectures on
Machiavelli that this seemed to me an amoral (and therefore evil) position; my
colleague tried to make the case that Machiavelli had a moral end in view and
was therefore a serious ethical arguer. I don’t want to rehash that argument,
but simply state here the obvious point that Machiavelli clearly does not
believe that any moral education in the Prince is necessary (if you agree with
me because morality is irrelevant; if you agree with my colleague’s argument,
because the moral ends, like the unification of Italy or the economic well
being of the citizens, are self-evident). If he can manipulate Kratos with sufficient skill, cunning, flexibility,
cruelty, and practical intelligence (what Machiavelli calls virtu),
then everything will be well. Hence the old observation about Machiavelli, that
there is no virtue in virtu.
This is a decisive break with the older tradition because it
emphatically shifts the major emphasis in political theory away from the moral
education of the ruler towards the practically efficient application of
political force to ensure the survival and the continuing power of the
government. It suggests, in effect, that the way in which politics is in fact
conducted is more important than the way politics ought to be conducted.
Put another way, we can say that for the ancient Greeks the
supreme question of politics was the way in which virtue in the ruler must
guide his or her use of force so as to produce justice. Thus, they focus, above
all, on the education of the ruler in morality. For Machiavelli the supreme
question in politics is the effective use of force to gain short-term success
(which means maintaining or increasing one’s immediate power). He concentrates
all his attention upon questions relating to that issue, either ignoring
morality as irrelevant or else assuming that the moral ends are so self-evident
that the Prince doesn’t need to consider them (or his education doesn’t have to
include any serious moral component).
In a similar manner Hobbes pays no attention to the moral
qualities of the sovereign. He seems to assume that, if the sovereign has all
the power, his self-interest in having a powerful state will persuade him to
leave his subjects alone so that they can make lots of money and keep the blood
of the state circulating. The distribution of political power is, for Hobbes,
the key question. Educating people to use it properly is largely irrelevant
because the moral questions, such as they are, are self-evident. Besides,
there’s no point in relying upon moral awareness of the rulers, simply because,
although Hobbes admired virtue, he didn’t think there was enough of it to go around
to make modern government moral in any traditional
sense of the word.
Rousseau’s position is very different. He is concerned, above all,
with achieving the correct balance of state power and morality. For him, as for
so many of his contemporaries, moral freedom is the most vital characteristic
of the human individual and any check on that is unwelcome oppression. As we
saw, Rousseau strives to deal with this question in a new and very influential
way: the power (Kratos) must belong to all people
equally. If they are educated sufficiently as rational creatures, share common
traditions, and can conveniently meet in an assembly of all citizens to enact
legislation (which determines the application of power), then the proper
combination of force and morality will be achieved and justice will rule the
state (a justice which provides freedom for all because they all participate
equally in it determining the application of force).
One of Rousseau’s most distinctive contributions to this debate
is, of course, his strong sense, that the ideal combination of Kratos and Ethos, the balance on which real justice
depends, is possible only in a republic run by a majoritarian
democracy. And most of Rousseau’s pessimism about such an arrangement stems
from his realization that this organization places too high a responsibility on
the individual citizen and creates far too tempting a scenario for government
to take over. His pessimism amounts to a clear sense that in such a republican majoritarian democracy the balance of power will shift to
those who are not ruled by Ethos but rather by self-interest, vanity, and so
on. And thus the realities of how people are will probably overwhelm any
possibilities for realizing what they ought to be.
Kant’s famous admiration for Rousseau comes, in large part, from
Rousseau’s insistence on the importance of personal and public morality (an
ethics based on reason and the choice to live by its rules made by free,
independent, self-reliant individuals) in the modern state. But Kant is much
more cautious about just what can and cannot be done, and he has no recourse to
some utopian model along Rousseau’s line. Kant fully acknowledges that what
goes on in the name of politics is largely as Machiavelli described it: amoral
self-interest. At the same time, Kant holds out the hope that Ethos--the moral
guiding of political force--must form a part of political action.
So Kant’s task, as an Enlightenment moralist, is to show how in
the modern state moral considerations are still of central importance as a
means of guiding Kratos. He is attempting to address
the old question--as ancient for us as the Old Testament, Odyssey, and
the Oresteia: Why should a powerful politician
pay any attention to moral issues? In terms of the brief retrospective I have
sketched out, Kant might be seen as attempting to show that Machiavelli and
Hobbes were wrong: the analysis of the modern political state cannot simply
focus on power arrangements and strategies for efficient applications of power.
As a moralist, Kant insists that politics is not just a matter of
prudence (i.e., material success in getting one’s way in the daily conflicts of
the political world). There must, by contrast, be what he calls “a limiting
condition of politics,” so that political affairs are in the command of the
moral politician, “one who so interprets the principles of political prudence
that they can be coherent with morality” (128).
This position is central to Kant’s call for universal peace,
because, as he points out repeatedly, if all statesmen rely only on political
prudence (on Machiavellian or Hobbesian principles),
then there is no ground for any international cooperation, because power
struggles between competing independent states will determine all politics.
Only the clear recognition of a commitment to a universal rational moral duty
can achieve the reconciliation he sees as essential to peace:
Even a continent that feels itself to be superior to another, regardless of whether or not the latter stands in the way of the former, will not fail to exercise the means of increasing its power, plundering and conquering. Thus, all theoretical plans for civil, international, and cosmopolitan rights dissolve into empty, impractical ideals; by contrast, a practice that is based on empirical principles of human nature and that does not regard it demeaning to formulate its maxims in accord with the way of the world [i.e., in accordance with universal moral laws] can alone hope to find a secure foundation for its structure of political prudence. (128)
Parenthetically, what’s interesting about Kant in this regard, of
course, is that he is the first thinker we have read seriously to consider the
question of permanent peace between nations (although Rousseau briefly hints at
this in the Discourse on Inequality). All of the others have more or
less assumed that warfare between states is a given fact of life and that,
therefore, in organizing the state we need above all to assume acts of
aggression from outside the polis.
What Kant wants us to realize is that there are important reasons
for believing that submitting our prudential strategies, our efficient
applications of political might, to the scrutiny of moral evaluation and
adjusting our prudential political decisions in the light of such evaluation is
something we ought to do. Everything in this position
depends upon our accepting the central claim Kant makes in all of these essays:
that there are firm grounds for acknowledging such a role for rational
morality.
To persuade that there are such firm grounds Kant puts forward a
number of points. Some of the more important are as follows:
First, Kant repeatedly puts us a the
painful situation of having to think about the consequences of rejecting his
view of world history. Since we all, as rational
beings, want world peace, since we, in our freedom, think that this is
something we ought to strive for, how is it to be achieved? This urgent desire
makes no sense, Kant argues, in a world that is mechanically governed and in
which the concept of moral freedom, as he defines it, is therefore meaningless
(128). Thus, to reject Kant’s moral interpretation of history is to be thrown
into a difficult situation of grappling with a universal moral desire for peace
without any means to achieve it (except perhaps by accident). Only faith in the
sort of rational moral progress of the sort he proposes answers to the free
moral desires of human beings.
Second, if we accept Kant’s vision of such rational moral
progress, then any politics based merely on prudence (on self-interested use of
power for national or personal survival) is going to defeat such progress
(129). For then the conduct of politics is ruled, not by universal moral
maxims, but by the survival strategies he lists on p. 130: pure Machiavellian
principles designed to ensure the forceful success through deceit, denial,
opportunism, and so on.
Third, Kant also makes the empirical point (which I tried to
stress in discussions of Machiavelli) that an examination of the facts of
history does not necessarily establish clearly that prudential politics is, in
fact, successful. Machiavellian tactics employed to achieve a particular aim
can, as often as not, prove self-defeating. Any practical political measure is
going to have an uncertain outcome. Therefore, we cannot and should not base
any moral desire for perpetual peace upon it.
Four, Kant also makes the deterministic argument (which is, as we
shall see, central to Marx), that if we do not, in fact, put moral
considerations into our political decisions making, then history will
eventually force us to do that anyway. The inexorable process of history, which
will very gradually bring about an increasing enlightenment and a cosmopolitan
world federation, is not something we can finally resist. Thus, in effect, he
is claiming history is on his side, no matter what we do. However, as rational
beings we have a moral obligation to assist this historical process “to make
the state of public right actual, though only through an unending process of
approximation to it. . . .” (139). One might want to cite environmental
awareness as one rational point which history is forcing us to acknowledge,
whether we approve of it or not.
It is worth nothing that this last point, about the inevitable
progression of history, has very ancient roots in the Old Testament notion that
God is on Israel’s side, that He has a covenant with the faithful, and that He
will lead them to the promised land. God’s providence,
acting through history, will resolve issues eventually; however, that does not
release the individual Israelite from the religious obligation to follow the
rules, to contribute to the progress of history.
Kant has, of course, thoroughly secularized this notion--seeing
perpetual peace as the end goal and a rational idea working itself out in
history as the engine of progress. But we should alert ourselves as to the
extent to which Kant’s ethics and his view of history has roots in some of the
most deeply held and ancient convictions of Western civilization (particularly
the Protestant version of those beliefs).
Whether we find Kant’s position on these matters entirely
persuasive or not, we cannot avoid the fact that the position he has outlined
in this essay has been enormously influential. While our faith in the gradual
enlightenment forced upon us by history may be considerably more tenuous than
his (and his is far from robust), it seems that many of us still place our best
hopes for world peace on a proper balance of force and morality of the sort
that Kant suggests. We may have grown quite cynical about many aspects of
domestic politics, but we are still, to a greater or less extent, faithful to
Kant’s notion that if we want to foster international peace, we must recognize
our rational obligations to all other human beings, difficult and expensive and
unwelcome as such steps may be. Our desire to have international leaders who
commit crimes against humanity brought to the bar of justice is a clear
expression of this faith.
At a time when immigration policies and Canada’s commitment to
peace-keeping missions and foreign aid are under attack, reading Kant’s essay
is a powerful reminder of why these practical political measures matter from
the moral standpoint. For we still have to be prepared to meet the challenge of
Thrasymachus in the opening of the Republic
that the only valuable political stance is that justice is the interests of the
stronger, that might makes right, that we have no moral obligations, only
imperatives of power.